Theorem21.35
The set of all constructible real numbers forms a subfield of the field of real numbers.
📚 The CoCalc Library - books, templates and other resources
Important: to view this notebook properly you will need to execute the cell above, which assumes you have an Internet connection. It should already be selected, or place your cursor anywhere above to select. Then press the "Run" button in the menu bar above (the right-pointing arrowhead), or press Shift-Enter on your keyboard.
ParseError: KaTeX parse error: \newcommand{\lt} attempting to redefine \lt; use \renewcommand
In ancient Greece, three classic problems were posed. These problems are geometric in nature and involve straightedge-and-compass constructions from what is now high school geometry; that is, we are allowed to use only a straightedge and compass to solve them. The problems can be stated as follows.
Given an arbitrary angle, can one trisect the angle into three equal subangles using only a straightedge and compass?
Given an arbitrary circle, can one construct a square with the same area using only a straightedge and compass?
Given a cube, can one construct the edge of another cube having twice the volume of the original? Again, we are only allowed to use a straightedge and compass to do the construction.
After puzzling mathematicians for over two thousand years, each of these constructions was finally shown to be impossible. We will use the theory of fields to provide a proof that the solutions do not exist. It is quite remarkable that the long-sought solution to each of these three geometric problems came from abstract algebra.
First, let us determine more specifically what we mean by a straightedge and compass, and also examine the nature of these problems in a bit more depth. To begin with, a straightedge is not a ruler. We cannot measure arbitrary lengths with a straightedge. It is merely a tool for drawing a line through two points. The statement that the trisection of an arbitrary angle is impossible means that there is at least one angle that is impossible to trisect with a straightedge-and-compass construction. Certainly it is possible to trisect an angle in special cases. We can construct a angle; hence, it is possible to trisect a angle. However, we will show that it is impossible to construct a angle. Therefore, we cannot trisect a angle.
A real number is if we can construct a line segment of length in a finite number of steps from a segment of unit length by using a straightedge and compass.
The set of all constructible real numbers forms a subfield of the field of real numbers.
Let and be constructible numbers. We must show that and () are also constructible numbers. We can assume that both and are positive with It is quite obvious how to construct and To find a line segment with length we assume that and construct the triangle in Figure 21.36 such that triangles and are similar. Since the line segment has length A similar construction can be made if We will leave it as an exercise to show that the same triangle can be used to construct for
If is a constructible number, then is a constructible number.
In Figure 21.38 the triangles and are similar; hence, or
By Theorem 21.35, we can locate in the plane any point that has rational coordinates and We need to know what other points can be constructed with a compass and straightedge from points with rational coordinates.
Let be a subfield of
If a line contains two points in then it has the equation where and are in
If a circle has a center at a point with coordinates in and a radius that is also in then it has the equation where and are in
Let and be points on a line whose coordinates are in If then the equation of the line through the two points is which has the form If then the equation of the line through the two points is given by
which can also be put into the proper form.
To prove the second part of the lemma, suppose that is the center of a circle of radius Then the circle has the equation
This equation can easily be put into the appropriate form.
Starting with a field of constructible numbers we have three possible ways of constructing additional points in with a compass and straightedge.
To find possible new points in we can take the intersection of two lines, each of which passes through two known points with coordinates in
The intersection of a line that passes through two points that have coordinates in and a circle whose center has coordinates in with radius of a length in will give new points in
We can obtain new points in by intersecting two circles whose centers have coordinates in and whose radii are of lengths in
The first case gives no new points in since the solution of two equations of the form having coefficients in will always be in The third case can be reduced to the second case. Let
be the equations of two circles, where and are in for These circles have the same intersection as the circle
and the line
The last equation is that of the chord passing through the intersection points of the two circles. Hence, the intersection of two circles can be reduced to the case of an intersection of a line with a circle.
Considering the case of the intersection of a line and a circle, we must determine the nature of the solutions of the equations
If we eliminate from these equations, we obtain an equation of the form where and are in The coordinate of the intersection points is given by
and is in where We have proven the following lemma.
Let be a field of constructible numbers. Then the points determined by the intersections of lines and circles in lie in the field for some in
A real number is a constructible number if and only if there exists a sequence of fields
such that with and In particular, there exists an integer such that
The existence of the 's and the 's is a direct consequence of Lemma 21.40 and of the fact that
The field of all constructible numbers is an algebraic extension of
As we can see by the field of constructible numbers, not every algebraic extension of a field is a finite extension.
We are now ready to investigate the classical problems of doubling the cube and squaring the circle. We can use the field of constructible numbers to show exactly when a particular geometric construction can be accomplished.
Given the edge of the cube, it is impossible to construct with a straightedge and compass the edge of the cube that has twice the volume of the original cube. Let the original cube have an edge of length 1 and, therefore, a volume of 1. If we could construct a cube having a volume of 2, then this new cube would have an edge of length However, is a zero of the irreducible polynomial over hence,
This is impossible, since 3 is not a power of 2.
Suppose that we have a circle of radius 1. The area of the circle is therefore, we must be able to construct a square with side This is impossible since and consequently are both transcendental. Therefore, using a straightedge and compass, it is not possible to construct a square with the same area as the circle.
Trisecting an arbitrary angle is impossible. We will show that it is impossible to construct a angle. Consequently, a angle cannot be trisected. We first need to calculate the triple-angle formula for the cosine:
The angle can be constructed if and only if is constructible. Let Then By the triple-angle formula for the cosine,
Therefore, is a zero of This polynomial has no factors in and hence is irreducible over Thus, Consequently, cannot be a constructible number.
Algebraic number theory uses the tools of algebra to solve problems in number theory. Modern algebraic number theory began with Pierre de Fermat (1601–1665). Certainly we can find many positive integers that satisfy the equation Fermat conjectured that the equation has no positive integer solutions for He stated in the margin of his copy of the Latin translation of Diophantus' Arithmetica that he had found a marvelous proof of this theorem, but that the margin of the book was too narrow to contain it. Building on work of other mathematicians, it was Andrew Wiles who finally succeeded in proving Fermat's Last Theorem in the 1990s. Wiles's achievement was reported on the front page of the New York Times.
Attempts to prove Fermat's Last Theorem have led to important contributions to algebraic number theory by such notable mathematicians as Leonhard Euler (1707–1783). Significant advances in the understanding of Fermat's Last Theorem were made by Ernst Kummer (1810–1893). Kummer's student, Leopold Kronecker (1823–1891), became one of the leading algebraists of the nineteenth century. Kronecker's theory of ideals and his study of algebraic number theory added much to the understanding of fields.
David Hilbert (1862–1943) and Hermann Minkowski (1864–1909) were among the mathematicians who led the way in this subject at the beginning of the twentieth century. Hilbert and Minkowski were both mathematicians at Göttingen University in Germany. Göttingen was truly one the most important centers of mathematical research during the last two centuries. The large number of exceptional mathematicians who studied there included Gauss, Dirichlet, Riemann, Dedekind, Noether, and Weyl.
André Weil answered questions in number theory using algebraic geometry, a field of mathematics that studies geometry by studying commutative rings. From about 1955 to 1970, Alexander Grothendieck dominated the field of algebraic geometry. Pierre Deligne, a student of Grothendieck, solved several of Weil's number-theoretic conjectures. One of the most recent contributions to algebra and number theory is Gerd Falting's proof of the Mordell-Weil conjecture. This conjecture of Mordell and Weil essentially says that certain polynomials in have only a finite number of integral solutions.